Icone social AHP

Can realism allow pluralism and contingency? Colloque dédié à une discussion du nouveau livre de Hasok Chang, Realism for realistic people, en présence et avec la contribution de l’auteur

Mercredi 19 octobre 2022 - 09:00 - Jeudi 20 octobre 2022 - 13:00
Nancy, Université de Lorraine, site Libération, salle internationale
Argumentaire: 


Les 19 et 20 octobre 2022, aura lieu à Nancy un colloque international issu du programme de recherche « MultiScienceS » piloté par Léna Soler aux Archives Henri Poincaré.
Le colloque sera consacré à une discussion du nouveau livre, très attendu, du philosophe et historien des sciences Hasok Chang :

Realism for realistic people. A New Pragmatist Philosophy of Science (à paraitre peu après chez Cambridge University Press), en présence de Hasok Chang

Question directrice des réflexions proposée aux intervenants : Can realism allow pluralism and contingency?

Hasok Chang fera deux communications, l’une pour introduire le colloque, l’autre pour le clore, et il répondra à chaque intervention.


Intervenants

Paul Hoyningen-Huene (Zürich / Hanovre)
Catherine Kendig (Michigan / Hanovre)
Ilkka Niiniluoto (Helsinki)
Jamie Shaw (Hanovre)
Léna Soler (Nancy)
Sophie Veigl (Vienne)
Jack Wright (Cambridge / Gothenburg)
Sjoerd Zwart (Delft)

(Programme et résumés des interventions ci-dessous)

Evénement en présence in situ (pas de possibilité d’assister à distance)

91 Avenue de la Libération, 3ème étage, Salle Internationale, 54000 Nancy

Organisé par Léna Soler (Nancy) et Sjoerd Zwart (Delft), avec le soutien des Archives Henri-Poincaré - Philosophie et Recherches sur les Sciences et les Technologies (AHP-PReST), de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme Lorraine (MSHL), du Conseil scientifique de l’université de Lorraine, et du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique (CNRS).


Pour tout renseignement : lena.soler<at>univ-lorraine.fr
 

Présentation du livre et de l’auteur par l’éditeur

In this innovative book, Hasok Chang constructs a philosophy of science for ‘realistic people’ interested in understanding and promoting the actual practices of inquiry in science and other knowledge-focused areas of life. Inspired by pragmatist philosophy, he reconceives the very notions of reality and truth on the basis of his concept of the ‘operational coherence’ of epistemic activities, and offers new pragmatist conceptions of truth and reality as operational ideals achievable in actual scientific practice. Rejecting the version of scientific realism that is concerned with claiming that our theories correspond to an ultimate reality, he proposes instead an ‘activist realism’: a commitment to do all that we can actually do to improve our knowledge of realities. His book will appeal to scholars and students in philosophy, science and the history of science, and all who are concerned about the place of science and empirical truth in society.

Hasok Chang is the Hans Rausing Professor of History and Philosophy of Science at the University of Cambridge. He is the author of Inventing Temperature: Measurement and Scientific Progress (2004), joint winner of the 2006 Lakatos Award, and of Is Water H2O? Evidence, Realism and Pluralism (2012).

Ajoutons que ce dernier ouvrage a remporté en 2013 le “Fernando Gil International Prize for the Philosophy of Science”, et que Hasok Chang s’est en outre vu attribuer, en 2021, le “Abraham Prize for History of Physics” de l’American Physical Society.
 

Deux points de vue sur le livre

“In this bold and wide-ranging new book, Hasok Chang provides a cornucopia of new ideas that challenge deeply-entrenched ways of thinking about scientific practice. He shows how insights of views that are often taken to be at odds with one another can be fruitfully combined in his own distinctive version of pragmatism. A tour de force.”
Philip Kitcher - Emeritus, Columbia University

“It is a challenging task for philosophy of science to understand science in its subtlety and complexity. In this book, Hasok Chang achieves even more than that. His endeavour to make knowledge active is an inspiring contribution to reworking and improving the epistemic framework of science.”
Martin Carrier - Bielefield University

 
Programme: 


Wednesday the 19th October
 

CHAIR

Ilkka Niiniluoto (Helsinki)

09:00 ­– 9:30

Opening of the conference by Léna Soler (Nancy)

09:30 ­– 10:00

Introduction of the conference by Hasok Chang (Cambridge)

10:00 – 11:00

-Catherine Kendig (Michigan / Hannover)

Metaphysical presuppositions realistic people use to be realists and why they matter for assessing knowledge as meaningful

-Reply by Hasok Chang and general discussion

11:00 11:15

Break

11:15 – 12:15

-Léna Soler (Nancy)

Incompatible judgments about the operational coherence and success of competing epistemic systems of practice: What should we do to be faithful to the pragmatist, realistic and pluralist spirit of Chang’s philosophy of science?

-Reply by Hasok Chang and general discussion

12:15 – 13:15

-Sjoerd Zwart (Delft)

Activist Realism from the Engineering Perspective: Business as usual or purging correspondence all the way down?

-Reply by Hasok Chang and general discussion

13:15 14:30

Lunch

CHAIR

Paul Hoyningen-Huene (Zürich / Hannover)

14:30 – 15:30

-Ilkka Niiniluoto (Helsinki)

Reality, truth, and pluralism: scientific realism vs. pragmatism

-Reply by Hasok Chang and general discussion

15:30 – 16:30

-Sophie Veigl (Vienna)

Active knowledge and activist knowledge: where realistic realism and feminist epistemology meet

-Reply by Hasok Chang and general discussion

16:30 16:45

Break

16:45 – 17:45

-Jack Wright (Cambridge / Gothenburg)

What does a realistic realist philosophy of science policy look like?

-Reply by Hasok Chang and general discussion


Thursday the 20th October
 

CHAIR

Catherine Kendig (Michigan / Hannover)

­08:30 – 9:30

-Paul Hoyningen-Huene (Zürich / Hannover)

Pluralism, Monism, and Hasok Chang: On Realism for Realistic People

-Reply by Hasok Chang and general discussion

9:30 – 10:30

-Jamie Shaw (Hannover)

How Unrestricted Should Inquiry Be? Chang and the Limits of Pluralism

-Reply by Hasok Chang and general discussion

10:30 10:45

Break

10:45 – 11:15

Conclusion of the conference by Hasok Chang (Cambridge)

CHAIR

Sjoerd Zwart (Delft)

11:15 – 12:00

General discussion

12:00 – 13:00

Lunch

 

Résumés: 


Paul Hoyningen-Huene (Leibniz Universität Hannover and Universität Zürich)

Pluralism, Monism, and Hasok Chang: On Realism for Realistic People

I fully share Chang’s objections to the traditional correspondence theory of truth with all the consequences this theory has for philosophy (of science). However, I propose a therapy different from his. I propose one should disentangle the two heterogenous elements in the traditional framing of the correspondence theory in analytic philosophy: the correspondence idea on the one hand and metaphysical realism on the other. Instead, the correspondence idea can be used in conjunction with many different ontologies. Given the operationality of this rejuvenated correspondence theory, the main need for an alternative theory of truth disappears. In addition, the pragmatist theory of truth seems not convincing in some areas of its intended application. Finally, I question Chang’s monism on the metaphilosophical level which is manifest by his defense of pragmatism. Why should we not extend the intellectually liberating pluralism that Chang defends on the object level concerning truth, reality, progress, etc. to the metaphilosophical level with the same liberating effect?
 

Catherine Kendig (Department of Philosophy, Michigan State University / Visiting Researcher, Centre for Ethics and Law in the Life Sciences (CELLS), Leibniz Universität Hannover)

Metaphysical presuppositions realistic people use to be realists and why they matter for assessing knowledge as meaningful

In Realism for Realistic People, Hasok Chang provides a guide for how we might be better realists. The standard realist’s reliance on a reality that exists out there in the noumenal world, is swapped for a reality that is always and only phenomenal. No more theories of truth that rely on correspondence with a reality that is inaccessible to us. Instead, reality and truth are obtained through operational coherence. I agree with Chang that operational coherence provides a useful means to evaluate the quality of knowledge. However, my concern is that it does not furnish a way to adjudicate between operationally coherent systems that should be valued, those that systematically omit some types of information which are deemed unnecessary, or those based on entrenched problematic beliefs. After a brief critique of Chang’s reliance on operational coherence, I offer a few friendly suggestions which, I hope, will allow us to adjudicate between operationally coherent systems that should be valued and those that should be discarded.

I illustrate my concern with reference to metaphysical presuppositions about species, (including species stability and cohesion), the reliance on which secures operational coherence. My suggestion is that we need to attend to the metaphysical commitments practitioners hold, as well as the methods they use, and the aims they rely upon to pursue coherent systems. In the case of species, accurate attributions of species-hood ultimately depend on accurate metaphysical presuppositions, which are themselves tacit in the putative explanations of stability that are adopted. But, as I will show, stability is liable to be misattributed if the mechanisms of stability are erroneously determined. Stability cannot be used to determine whether or not the clusters themselves are natural. This is because any kind attribution that relies on these clusters is anchored to a particular metaphysical picture of the world that it takes to be natural without being able to arbitrate between different candidate pictures of the world.
 

Ilkka Niiniluoto (Professor emeritus of Theoretical Philosophy, University of Helsinki, Finland)

Reality, truth, and pluralism: scientific realism vs. pragmatism

Hasok Chang’s new book Realism for Realistic People (2022) is a rich and sophisticated improvement of neopragmatist accounts of philosophy of science. His references to my Critical Scientific Realism (CSR, 1999) give an opportunity for dialogue and fruitful confrontation. I will raise several questions and potential objections to his operational definition of reality and truth. First, Chang follows pragmatists in arguing that Kantian things-in-themselves are not needed. But how can he explain that realities are both mind-framed and mind-uncontrolled without assuming something ontological about the noumenal mind-independent WORLD? In CSR, the WORLD is a lawlike flux of causal processes, where physical objects and their kinds and other entities (fields) are identifiable by their physical properties and spatio-temporal continuity, and the conceptualized world-versions WL (for various languages L) are mind-framed by L and mind-uncontrolled (grounded) by the WORLD. Secondly, is Chang’s operational definition too positive?:We often stumble on hard realities which prevent our activities or make them less successful. Thirdly, for Chang realness and truth have degrees, but the notion of approximate truth is a ”watering-down move”. In CSR, truthlikeness is a tool of critical realism against absolute and naive realism. Fourthly, is Chang’s account too restrictive? Some past objects (e.g. dinosaurs) are abductively accessible to us by the causal effects or traces that they have left; yet many of them were real but left no traces. What present coherent operational epistemic activities could rely on the past existence of dinosaurs? Perhaps classification of dinosaur fossils, but what about the classification of pictures of unicorns? Fifthly, could all particular grains of sand, raindrops, mosquitos, stars, black holes and unobservable objects in distant galaxies be relevant to human practices? Sixthly, is Chang’s pluralist account too permissive? Many human tribes have led harmonious and successful lives with animistic beliefs in angels, fairies, brownies, witches, and evil spirits. In science, phlogiston had some successful applications, but as a description of the process of combustion it cannot be accepted in our world view. Seventhly, CSR defends conceptual pluralism which is compatible with the correspondence theory of truth: world-versions WL are L-structures, and truth in WL is defined by Tarski’s model theory. But as conceptualizations of the same reality these world-versions cannot contradict each other (even though beliefs in different languages can); and truth about WL is also truth about the WORLD. There is no single ideal language L (Sellars’s “Peirceish”) which captures all of the WORLD. Eightly, pragmatism is interested in the human world constituted by our practices, but human existence is only a tiny fragment of the long history of the universe. The conception of the WORLD expresses this humility with respect to the mind-independent reality. We can investigate it by introducing conceptual schemes as mediating steps in our search for objective knowledge. And we are also responsible for the (often unintended and non-conceptualized) causal effects of our actions on nature (pollution, climate change, loss of biodiversity). Ninthly, pragmatism seems to be most appropriate as a philosophy of human practical action, including applied science, technology in the broad sense, and engineering. Epistemic conceptions (e.g. credibility, confirmation, assertibility, operational coherence), which do not satisfy Tarski’s T-equivalence, may be highly valuable as criteria of reality and truth but they should not be called by the name “truth”. Tenthly, perhaps scientific realism and pragmatism can live in peaceful co-existence, if the revitalized Jamesian activity-oriented coherence conceptions are understood to express notions that are different from the classical realist’s reality and truth - such as tools and their effectiveness in Dewey’s instrumentalism. This would give a motivation for pluralism: tool-like realities deserve to be conserved if they help us to do important things in certain contexts.
 

Jamie Shaw (Institut für Philosophie, Leibniz Universität Hannover)

How Unrestricted Should Inquiry Be? Chang and the Limits of Pluralism

In Hasok Chang’s new book, Realism for Realistic People, he outlines a theory of inquiry. This theory contains the same core as those of his pragmatist ancestors, most notably C.S. Peirce and John Dewey, where inquiry is stimulated by the presence of a problem and resolved when the problem appears to be solved. The goal of this paper is to critically investigate Chang’s theory of inquiry. After showing how Chang’s conception of inquiry is ambiguous, as it does not clearly define restrictions upon inquiry, I contend that there exists a tension between his view of inquiry and his activist realism. Erasing this tension, I claim, requires lifting the restrictions Chang places upon inquiry thus distancing himself from his pragmatist forefathers.
 

Léna Soler (Université de Lorraine, Archives Henri-Poincaré - Philosophie et Recherches sur les Sciences et les Technologies, Nancy)

Incompatible judgments about the operational coherence and success of competing epistemic systems of practice: What should we do to be faithful to the pragmatist, realistic and pluralist spirit of Chang’s philosophy of science?

Operational coherence is the pivotal notion, and plays essential constitutive roles, in the inspiring and sophisticated pragmatist philosophy of science designed by Hasok Chang in Realism for Realistic People (RRP). In the “realistic” or “operationalist” spirit of Chang’s framework, any judgment about whether or not, or to what extent, a given ingredient of a given inquiry counts as knowledge, can be considered as real, is legitimately taken as true, or should be viewed as a progress, is based on judgments of operational coherence, and thus presupposes such judgments.

My aim, in this talk, is to start from the refined characterization of operational coherence offered by Chang in RRP, and to discuss some possible difficulties of its application to particular tokens of epistemic practices. These difficulties concern two related kinds of judgments: assessments of the (degree of) operational coherence, and evaluations of the success, of a system of practice or an activity involved in an ongoing epistemic inquiry considered in a dynamical perspective. I want to explore the possibility of conflicts, if not of irreconcilable disagreements, at the level of such judgments. To address this possibility is crucial regarding what matters to Chang’s activist and realist philosophy of science. For an activist realism à la Chang intends to help epistemic actors to maximize active knowledge, and to maximize active knowledge means to maximize the operational coherence of epistemic practices and the actual success of designed-for-success activities. Accordingly, as far as judgments of operational coherence and success are unproblematic and consensual, what the activist realist prescribes to do is not problematic. But what if the corresponding judgments were problematic and not consensual? What would the realistic pluralist recommend to do?

To substantiate the philosophical points, I will rely on quantum mechanics as an illustration, mobilizing a case that I take to be especially interesting as a means to investigate crucial aspects of Chang’s pragmatist philosophy of science. This case involves two presently alive, predictively equivalent but mutually incompatible theoretical frameworks (or paradigms) and systems of practice. One is the orthodox quantum physics that became hegemonic at the turn of the 1930s. The other is an alternative, fringe quantum physics introduced by David Bohm in 1952 and subsequently developed by Bohmians until today. I refer to the latter physics or paradigm or system of practice as “BQP”, and to the former as “NQP” – where the “N” stands for “Neurakian”, a term forged from the names of John von Neumann and Paul Dirac, coined in order to have a qualifier symmetric to “Bohmian”. Once reconceptualized by means of Chang’s categories, this “N/B-QP case” can claim to exemplify irreconcilable disagreements between Neurakian and Bohmian epistemic agents about (at least some) judgments of operational coherence and empirical success. This case is especially interesting in two respects. First, given that NQP and BQP are predictively indistinguishable, we have a configuration that is potentially instructive regarding the aim of investigating and specifying Chang’s idea of what pragmatism and empiricism mean and amount to in practice, beyond the uncontroversial but restricted classical requirement of empirical adequacy (corroboration of predicted observations). What would be the additional requirements for assessing the quality of the non-predictive activities constitutive of NQP and BQP in a way that could pretend to be faithful to the empiricist stance as understood by Chang? Second, the N/B-QP case provides an interesting setting in order to discuss the intrinsic difficulties, and the concrete implementation in practice, of any resolutely pluralist philosophy of science of the type advocated by Chang. In the N/B-QP case, the two semantically and normatively incommensurable systems of practice under scrutiny involve two mutually contradictory descriptions of the same targeted object and convey two partially different but ultimately irreconcilable normative conceptions of physics, including partly irreconcilable conceptions of what is empirical knowledge in physics and what are the legitimate aims of physics. How is a realistic pluralist à la Chang going to cope with such kinds of semantic and normative incompatibilities?
 

Sophie Veigl (University of Vienna, Department of Philosophy)

Active knowledge and activist knowledge: where realistic realism and feminist epistemology meet

How realism and plurality can be accommodated is a question that sits at the core of the scientific pluralism debate. How do different, contradictory approaches make contact with what is “out there?” Another school of thought that has been dealing with this question within the philosophy of science is feminist philosophy of science. Proponents reject “capital R reality” and argue for a pluralization of research practices and theorizing to accommodate marginalized practices within the sciences. A rejection of “capital R reality” is also central to Hasok Chang’s most recent contribution to the scientific pluralism literature, Realism for Realistic People. So far (and maybe because these positions have much in common), the relation of both has not been extensively explored. Does feminist philosophy of science necessarily require Changian scientific pluralism? Does scientific pluralism a la Chang necessarily invoke the pluralization feminist philosophers have in mind? In this article, I aim at further exploring this relation, particularly explaining these positions’ relation when it comes to triangulating scientific pluralism, realism, and contingency within science.
 

Jack Wright (University of Cambridge and University of Gothenburg)

What does a realistic realist philosophy of science policy look like?

In his closing remarks Chang asks:

“How do we advance an improved theory of action fully incorporating values and judgements? How can my pragmatist philosophy of science be connected more convincingly with social epistemology and the sociology of knowledge?” (254)

My comment will partly address these questions by asking what realistic realism means for how we use the outputs of science in political and social decisions. I will argue that although realistic realism does a good job of describing what happens within science, it makes the utilisation of scientific knowledge in deliberations about social action more complicated. The traditional realist picture that Chang argues against (truth is correspondence, knowledge is true propositions, science provides knowledge) has a simple story to tell: deliberation about social action can draw on and be bounded by the true propositions given by science. How do conceptions of knowledge centred on operationally coherent activities and of truth based around facilitating such activities fit into deliberation about group action? Answering this question highlights the pragmatic issues with some of Chang’s attempts to redefine truth, reality, and realism.
 

Sjoerd Zwart (TPM, Delft, University of Technology, Netherlands)

Activist Realism from the Engineering Perspective: Business as usual or purging correspondence all the way down?

To a large extent Hasok Chang’s Realism for Realistic People (RRP) fits engineering practice well. The way engineers use scientific theories (parallel to the theories they develop) is characterized by instrumentalism. When bridges or apartments are built, engineers used Newtonian Mechanics, but if they need to hit tanks with laser beams from out of space they use Relativity Theory; engineers choose those scientific theories that are likely to help them to solve their technical problems. This comes close to the cumulative progress of science.

Being immersed in the design of academic engineering research and methodology for the last twenty years, I assess molecular engineering PhD research projects, like Chang, by their (operational) coherence. In my conceptualization, all atomic subprojects should produce deliverables that (for the chosen way to solve the problem) are necessary and together sufficient to produce the comprehensive end deliverable. I distinguish seven types of deliverables all with their own characteristic methods. Among these deliverables, descriptive knowledge, design and means-end knowledge, are the most frequent and important from an epistemological point of view. An engineering research project design has a high quality when it has the form of a means-end hierarchy of atomic subprojects typically of different types which all serve the purpose of the final deliverable of the project; only then it has a high operational coherence.

So far, RRP and engineering research practice fit very well. However, a first crack appears when one considers the descriptive type of a (sub)project. This type hinges for a large part on “correspondence realism” (although without supposing the strong Fallacy of Pre-Figuration), so heavily criticized in RRP. The need of truth by correspondence within an engineering project will be illustrated by a thought experiment of a 17th clockmaker. As a consequence of this example, I will sketch a difficulty with Chang's definition of truth on p. 167 by using a self-reference example.

The main purpose of this contribution is to diagnose the apparent problem of mismatch between RRP and the practice of engineering research, and to assess its epistemic weight. To do so I would like to discuss the following issues: the asymmetry of emphasis on purging correspondence regarding theories and on purging correspondence regarding phenomena (by systematic comparison in the RRP text); and the possibility, efficiency and coherence of rewriting all (innocent) phenomenal correspondence parlance into only action-language (if that exists). Finally, if time allows, I would like to expound my own epistemic position between the extremes of realism (correspondence all the way up) and pragmatism (coherence all the way down).